ADVERTISEMENT
  About the SA Blog Network













Doing Good Science

Doing Good Science


Building knowledge, training new scientists, sharing a world.
Doing Good Science Home

Incoherent ethical claims that give philosophers a bad rap

The views expressed are those of the author and are not necessarily those of Scientific American.


Email   PrintPrint



Every now and then, in the course of a broader discussion, some philosopher will make a claim that is rightly disputed by non-philosophers. Generally, this is no big deal — philosophers have just as much capacity to be wrong as other humans. But sometimes, the philosopher’s claim, delivered with an air of authority, is not only a problem in itself but also manages to convey a wrong impression about the relation between the philosophers and non-philosophers sharing a world.

I’m going to examine the general form of one such ethical claim. If you’re interested in the specific claim, you’re invited to follow the links above. We will not be discussing the specific claim here, nor the larger debate of which it is a part.

Claim: To decide to do X is always (or, at least, should always be) a very difficult and emotional step, precisely because it has significant ethical consequences.

Let’s break that down.

“Doing X has significant ethical consequences” suggests a consequentialist view of ethics, in which doing the right thing is a matter of making sure the net good consequences (for everyone affected, whether you describe them in terms of “happiness” or something else) outweigh the net bad consequences.

To say that doing X has significant ethical consequences is then to assert that (at least in the circumstances) doing X will make a significant contribution to the happiness or unhappiness being weighed.

In the original claim, the suggestion is that the contribution of doing X to the balance of good and bad consequences is negative (or perhaps that it is negative in many circumstances), and that on this account it ought to be a “difficult and emotional step”. But does this requirement make sense?

In the circumstances in which doing X shifts the balance of good and bad consequences to a net negative, the consequentialist will say you shouldn’t do X — and this will be true regardless of your emotions. Feeling negative emotions as you are deciding to do X will add more negative consequences, but they are not necessary: a calculation of the consequences of doing X versus not doing X will still rule out doing X as an ethical option even if you have no emotions associated with it at all.

On the other hand, in the circumstances in which doing X shifts the balance of good and bad consequences to a net positive, the consequentialist will say you should do X — again, regardless of your emotions. Here, feeling negative emotions as you are deciding to do X will add more negative consequences. If these negative emotions are strong enough, they run the risk of reducing the net positive consequences — which makes the claim that one should feel negative emotions (pretty clearly implied in the assertion that the decision to do X should be difficult) a weird claim, since these negative emotions would serve only to reduce the net good consequences of doing something that produces net good consequences in the circumstances.

By the way, this also suggests, perhaps perversely, a way that strong emotions could become a problem in circumstances in which doing X would otherwise clearly bring more negative consequences than positive ones: if the person contemplating doing X were to get a lot of happiness from doing X.

Now, maybe the idea is supposed to be that negative feelings associated with the prospect of doing X are supposed to be a brake if doing X frequently leads to more bad consequences than good ones. But I think we have to recognize feelings as consequences — as something that we need to take into account in the consequentialist calculus with which we evaluate whether doing X here is ethical or not. And that makes the claim that the feelings ought always to be negative, regardless of other features of the situation that make doing X the right thing, puzzling.

You could avoid worries about weighing feelings as consequences by shifting from a consequentialist ethical framework to something else, but I don’t think that’s going to be much help here.

Kantian ethics, for example, won’t pin the ethics of doing X to the net consequences, but instead it will come down to something like whether it is your duty to do X (where your duty is to respect the rational capacity in yourself and in others, to treat people as ends in themselves rather than as mere means). Your feelings are no part of what a Kantian would consider in judging whether your action is ethical or not. Indeed, Kantians stress that ethical acts are motivated by recognizing your duty precisely because feelings can be a distraction from behaving as we should.

Virtue ethicists, on the other hand, do talk about the agent’s feelings as ethically relevant. Virtuous people take pleasure in doing the right things and feel pain at the prospect of doing the wrong thing. However, if doing X is right under the circumstances, the virtuous people will feel good about doing X, not conflicted about it — so the claim that doing X should always be difficult and emotional doesn’t make much sense here. Moreover, virtue ethicists describe the process of becoming virtuous as one where behaving in virtuous ways usually precedes developing emotional dispositions to feel pleasure from acting virtuously.

Long story short, it’s hard to make sense of the claim “To decide to do X is always (or, at least, should always be) a very difficult and emotional step, precisely because it has significant ethical consequences” — unless really what is being claimed it that doing X is always unethical and you should always feel bad for doing X. If that’s the claim, though, emotions are pretty secondary.

But beyond the incoherence of the claim, here’s what really bugs me about it: It seems to assert that ethicists (and philosophers more generally) are in the business of telling people how to feel. That, my friends, is nonsense. Indeed, I’m on record prioritizing changes in unethical behavior over any interference with what’s in people’s hearts. How we behave, after all, has much more impact on our success in sharing a world with each other than how we feel.

This is not to say that I don’t recognize a likely connection between what’s in people’s hearts and how they behave. For example, I’m willing to bet that improvements in our capacity for empathy would likely lead to more ethical behavior.

But it’s hard to see as empathetic telling people they should generally feel bad for making a choice which under the circumstances is an ethical choice. If anything, requiring such negative emotions is a failure of empathy, and punitive to boot.

Clearly, there exist ethicists and philosophers who operate this way, but many of us try to do better. Indeed, it’s reasonable for you all to expect and demand that we do better.

Janet D. Stemwedel About the Author: Janet D. Stemwedel is an Associate Professor of Philosophy at San José State University. Her explorations of ethics, scientific knowledge-building, and how they are intertwined are informed by her misspent scientific youth as a physical chemist. Follow on Twitter @docfreeride.

The views expressed are those of the author and are not necessarily those of Scientific American.

Tags:



Previous: Soothing jellies More
Doing Good Science
Next: Engagement with science needs more than heroes




Rights & Permissions

Comments 10 Comments

Add Comment
  1. 1. Lacota 9:19 pm 03/16/2014

    I thought that was the difference between ethical and moral behavior. Ethical behavior is calculated and not emotional. I don’t speed because speeding is unlawful. I don’t feel bad when I speed I am just aware that it isn’t the right thing to do so I choose not to do it. On the other hand, a moral person would feel bad about speeding.

    I am also not clear of the connection between, “a very difficult and emotional step” and “feeling bad”.

    Finally, all sensory input (aside from olfaction) passes through the Limbic system and has an emotional context attached. It is therefore impossible to completely remove one’s self from one’s emotions. One can only change the emotional response one has to inputs (perhaps not even that depending on your view of free will).

    I guess the one problem I have with philosophy is how it sometimes seems to unburden itself of reality and speaks in terms of concepts as though they were independent of the substrate.

    Link to this
  2. 2. tuned 9:53 am 03/17/2014

    Avoid bad consequences, whether you feel good, bad or indifferent about it.

    Link to this
  3. 3. rkipling 3:28 pm 03/17/2014

    Asserting that anything is always the case brings the argument into question for me.

    Link to this
  4. 4. SamHall 4:47 pm 03/18/2014

    What if you feel good about doing something that is harmful and unethical to another person? For example, you tell your neighbor that his wife is having an affair. You feel righteous but he is harmed at something that is none of your business.
    Or the woman at a children’s party that forced a kid to eat a cookie. The kid knew he shouldn’t eat that kind of cookie, but she forced him to and he died from a allergic reaction.
    Do what is ethical, not what you feel good about.

    Link to this
  5. 5. italtrav 4:59 pm 03/18/2014

    This version of ethics shears off any recognition of passion or emotion in moral action on the belief that what is ethical can always be understood and stated as a rule. If that is so, then the morality of an action is rightly judged entirely on how well it follows the rule. However, this leaves out of the account of morality an important component, i.e. that a great part of the measure of the morality of an action is the self-sacrifice which attaches to it. We rightly regard good actions requiring minor self-denial as less morally significant than actions which require or result in, say, the ultimate sacrifice. So, deciding to summarily execute a coward on the field of battle both is and ought to always be a difficult and emotional step, precisely because it has significant ethical consequences. Were such a sentence to be meted out with either levity or casual indifference, the justness of the act would rightly be called into question. In brief, how one feels about what one does is an integral part of the intention, which is always an integral part of moral explanation.

    Link to this
  6. 6. Janet D. Stemwedel in reply to Janet D. Stemwedel 6:54 pm 03/18/2014

    Part of the point of this post is that not all ethical frameworks recognize intention (as opposed to, say, consequences) as ethically relevant.

    And (as SamHall’s examples suggest), there are surely instances in which one’s emotions, whether negative or positive, would be misleading as far as whether the action accompanying those emotions was ethical or not.

    Link to this
  7. 7. italtrav 7:55 pm 03/18/2014

    @Janet D. Stemwedel
    Ethical frameworks might differ as regards intention (I would argue that any which completely ignore it fail to understand their purported subject matter). But that doesn’t affect my response that the claim statement, “To decide to do X is always (or, at least, should always be) a very difficult and emotional step, precisely because it has significant ethical consequences,” is true for some situations and has the merit of encapsulating an important facet of the pre- or non-philosophical or naive viewpoint of ethics—the Aristotelian man-in-the-street, as it were.

    Link to this
  8. 8. Janet D. Stemwedel in reply to Janet D. Stemwedel 8:01 pm 03/18/2014

    @ italtrav,

    I think if you’re willing to grant that the claim needn’t be true for all values of X, I’m happy to grant that there are some values for which it might be a useful claim.

    (I’m still not sure a focus on what people should feel as opposed to how they should behave is especially productive, but then we’re taking strategy and grappling with questions that are likely to be empirical.)

    Link to this
  9. 9. rkipling 3:24 am 03/19/2014

    italtrav,

    Your assertion in the last sentence of @5 is not necessarily true.

    I appreciate your use of “Aristotelian man-in-the-street.” I had not seen that construction before. It is revealing.

    Link to this
  10. 10. nestord 1:31 pm 03/19/2014

    It might be that X is your duty in a Kantian sense. In that case, I think, any reasonable person who also happens to be a Kantian would have emotional difficulties. It was established that X is your duty so you ought to do it, but it is also true that it will have negative consequences. The Kantian would of course ignore any emotions and proceed to do X, but that doesn’t rule out the possibility of feeling those emotions knowing that your actions will have negative consequences

    Link to this

Add a Comment
You must sign in or register as a ScientificAmerican.com member to submit a comment.

More from Scientific American

Scientific American Special Universe

Get the latest Special Collector's edition

Secrets of the Universe: Past, Present, Future

Order Now >

X

Email this Article

X